Eisner, Elliot W. (2002). The Arts and the Creation of
Mind. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
258 pages
$35.00 (Cloth) ISBN 0300095236
Reviewed by James G. Henderson
Kent State University
An Overview
Elliot Eisner needs no introduction to the readers of this journal.
He is
well known for his many creative contributions to the education
field on arts-related topics. Eisner has provided cutting-edge
thinking for over thirty years on such questions as: how to
teach the arts, how is education a form of human artistry,
and how should educational artistry be researched. He
does not disappoint in this book; and, in fact, this text could
be viewed as the definitive statement of his career. He
summarizes all of the key educational arguments he has advanced
over the years with very concise terminology and cogent
rationales. The book is, in essence, a well-organized and
coherent set of essays on the following topics: the role of the
arts in transforming consciousness, visions and versions of arts
education, teaching the visual arts, what the arts teach and how
it shows, describing learning in the visual arts, the centrality
of curriculum and the function of standards, the educational uses
of assessment and evaluation in the arts, what education can
learn from the arts, and an agenda for research in arts
education. To make sure he is clearly understood, Eisner
concludes with a summary of his nine essays. In this final
chapter, he presents thirteen “important ideas” for
the future of educational research and practice. This
point-by-point declaration is not only a useful synopsis; it is
also an effective rhetorical method for conveying his educational
vision in a set of precisely written statements. Simply stated,
this is a must-read book for readers of this journal.
Given the complexity of Eisner’s arguments, there are
many ways to read his book. I will briefly provide two such
readings, and my comments are a reflection of my own scholarly
concerns. The fact that I take this course of action is a
testament to the power of Eisner’s essays. I would argue
that important educational texts—books that stand the test
of time—are generative in nature. They do not provide easy
answers to simplistic questions but, rather, foster a deepening
understanding of the education art. In one of his essays, Eisner
makes this hermeneutic point as follows:
The writer [as critic] starts the process of writing by seeing
and by having an emotional response that is then transformed into
words intended to capture the flavor of that response.
Thus…the writer starts with vision and ends with words.
The reader, however, starts with the writer’s words and
ends with vision. The circle is complete. (pp. 88-89)
I feel this brief quotation captures the spirit of
Eisner’s book and, in fact, of his entire career. In a
very basic way, Eisner practices what he preaches. He has a deep
feel for arts education and educational artistry. He eloquently
articulates this feeling as a vision for the future of the
profession, and he invites his reader to share in this vision in
his or her own way. As I read his book, two particular visions
came to mind. I share them now as my way of completing
“the circle” of Eisner’s words.
A Vision of Public Intellectuals
I’ve recently completed teaching a five-week summer
seminar that was organized around the following question:
Can one work as a public intellectual in the context of
one’s academic specialization? Eighteen doctoral
students from all of the major Ph.D. Programs in the College of
Education at Kent State University took the course. We began the
seminar by studying four topics with the assistance of selected
chapters from five books (Bender, 1993; Hadot, 2002; Kegan, 2000;
Klein, 1990; and Slattery and Rapp, 2003). The topics were:
- Providing intellectual leadership for transformative
learning.
- The importance of “interdisciplinarity” when
addressing pressing public problems in education and human
services.
- Professional ethics under “postmodern”
conditions.
- The meaning and spirit (the hermeneutics) of acquiring a
“Doctor of Philosophy” (Ph.D.)—of professing a
“love of wisdom.”
The level of enthusiasm in the seminar was a pleasant
surprise. The doctoral students were quite passionate in their
study of the four topics, and their final papers delved deeply
into the personal, professional, cultural and moral complexities
of the seminar’s organizing question. It was the type of
course where everyone claps at the end in celebration for the
quality of the learning that has occurred. In that moment of
applause, I was struck by the doctoral students’
determination to find a deeper purpose for their academic
socialization; and I can only hope that such a moment turns into
a lifelong passion. If it does, they may one day write a book
that will be different in its details but equal in spirit to
Eisner’s collective essays.
Eisner’s book serves as an inspirational model for
public intellectual work in several important ways. In his
introductory comments, he articulates a pressing public
problem:
The world that students now live in and that they will enter
as adults is riddled with ambiguities, uncertainties, the need to
exercise judgment in the absence of rule, and the press of the
feelingful as a source of information for making difficult
choices. (p. xii)
He then states that there are ways that art education, in
particular, and educational artistry, in general, can provide
educational solutions to this problem and that the purpose of his
essays is to explore these ways. And this is exactly what he
proceeds to do in unadorned, clear language. He writes for a
general audience on a significant public matter. He works out of
a broad interdisciplinary perspective and attempts to inspire
deep personal insights on important moral matters. Though he
possesses expertise as both an art educator and curriculum
scholar, he thinks beyond the confines of particular academic
communities. He works as a far-sighted humanist, not as a narrow
educational expert. He writes for all of our futures, and he
ends his book with these words:
Those of us who have worked in the arts, who have taught the
arts, who have tried to understand what the arts contribute to
the development of human consciousness can feel a sense of pride
that our legacy is one that attempts to engender life at its most
vital level. The arts make such vitality possible. They are
sources of deep enrichment for all of us. (p.241)
As I reflect on Eisner’s book, I imagine a future where
an increasing number of academics will work as public
intellectuals. I picture a time when texts like his will serve
as exemplars for doctoral socialization.
A Vision of Democratic Educators
I was inspired by another vision of our
educational future as I read Eisner’s essays. I imagine a
time when an increasing number of educators, functioning as
connoisseurs and critics of the democratic “good
life,” will reject the current dominant paradigm of
curriculum decision-making. This paradigm is based on a very
straightforward command-and-control logic associated with
approaching education as an efficient business. Educational
standards are clearly identified and translated into standardized
outputs, and curriculum is aligned to these outputs in order to
streamline student “achievement.” Students are
mandated to take periodic tests of these standardized outputs so
that there can be a proper public accounting of their educational
progress. The results of these standardized tests are publicized
and have several “high stakes” consequences,
including school districts’ financial support,
administrators’ job security, and students’ timely
grade promotion and graduation. Cuban (2003) summarizes three
key assumptions of this decision-making paradigm:
- They assumed that better management, rigorous academic
standards, increased competition among schools for students, and
incentives and penalties would produce better teaching and
learning and higher test scores.
- They assumed that the best measures of improved teaching and
learning are taking more academic subjects, scoring well on
standardized tests, securing credentials, and moving into skilled
jobs.
- They assumed that penalties and rewards get teachers to teach
better and students to learn more. (p.19)
I imagine a future where increasing numbers of educators will
daily work on cultivating their capacities to exercise
democratically wise curriculum judgments (Henderson and Kesson,
2004). Curriculum wisdom can be described as a
“doubled” problem solving. There is, first, the
effort to be practical—to solve the immediate
problem or problems one is facing. This is a context-specific
and fairly straightforward means/end way of operating:
admit there is a problem, work on defining the problem, decide
how to solve the problem, work on the solution, and periodically
evaluate the results of your actions. A wisdom orientation takes
this decision-making to a deeper level. The focus is still on
solving an immediate problem—after all, the concept of
wisdom denotes such practicality; but now, the goal is to solve
the problem with reference to a conception of the
“good” life. This is a more complicated
means/end and means/visionary end way of
operating. The search for practical solutions is transformed
into an aspiration to advance a critically informed moral
vision.
Democratic curriculum wisdom is based on a particular
“logic” of inquiry (Burke, 1994; Dewey 1938), which
can be described as the disciplined study of democracy as a moral
basis of living. “Democracy” is typically understood
as a type of government. To approach democracy as a way of
life—or, as Dewey (1989) puts it, “a moral standard
for personal conduct” (p.101)—is to extend a
democratic outlook to all aspects of one’s daily living.
Such an approach requires a sophisticated form of understanding
because there is no ultimate definition for “democratic
morality”—no final democratic doctrine. At best,
there are only informed interpretations. The educator must
acknowledge and work with the ambiguity and
plurality inherent in his or her search for the
“democratic good life.” Tracy (1987) provides
insight into this way of working. He argues that moral
understanding in the context of religious diversity is best
handled as a “plurality of interpretations and
methods.” (p.112) He explains:
We find ourselves with diverse religious classics among many
religious traditions. …The conflicts on how to interpret
religion, the conflicts caused by the opposing claims of the
religions themselves, and the internal conflicts within any great
religion all affect interpreters, whether they will it or not.
None of these conflicts is easily resolved, and no claim to
certainty, whether religionist or secularist, should pretend
otherwise. …Einstein once remarked that with the arrival
of the atomic age everything had changed except our thinking.
Unfortunately the remark is true. Perhaps contemporary
reflections on interpretation, with their emphasis on plurality
and ambiguity, are one more stumbling start, across the
disciplines, to try to change our usual ways of thinking. (pp.
112-114)
Interpretations of “democratic morality” begin at
the point where plurality and ambiguity are embraced; otherwise,
the resulting understanding cannot be “democratic.”
When religious morality is interpreted in the spirit of plurality
and ambiguity, it informs the “democratic good
life.” However, when religious morality is reduced to
rigid doctrines and ideological litmus tests (i.e., “true
beliefs”), a “democratic” way of life can only
be practiced by carefully separating church and state.
The future democratic educators I envision would
resonate with Eisner’s essays for a number of reasons.
They would applaud the way he quickly establishes critical
distance from the dominant paradigm of curriculum decision-making
in his introductory comments:
Efficiency is largely a virtue for the tasks we don’t
like to do; few of us like to eat a great meal efficiently or to
participate in a wonderful conversation efficiently, or indeed to
make love efficiently. What we enjoy the most we linger over. A
school system designed with an overriding commitment to
efficiency may produce outcomes that have little enduring
quality. (p. xiii)
They would agree with his definition of education as
“the process of learning to create ourselves” (p.3)
because they interpret curriculum as envisioning and enacting a
democratic good life. Like Eisner, they believe, “Humans,
of all living species, have the distinctive…ability to
create a culture through which those in their community can
grow” (p.3), and they think this broad
“cultural” approach to education is the best frame of
reference for curriculum problem solving.
These democratic educators would find
Eisner’s essays on artistry, evaluation, standards, and
research to be particularly enlightening and helpful. Because
they do not function as narrow, unimaginative technicians, they
would be drawn to Eisner’s definition of artistry:
“By artistry, I mean a form of practice informed by the
imagination that employs technique to select and organize
expressive qualities to achieve ends that are aesthetically
satisfying” (p. 49, author’s emphasis). This
definition captures the spirit of their wisdom orientation as
they attempt to interject an imaginative, visionary feel for the
democratic “good life” into the full range of their
curriculum practices, including designing, organizing, teaching,
and evaluating.
Eisner’s discussion of educational assessment and
evaluation confirms and supports their professional orientation.
Because they have established critical distance from the dominant
paradigm of curriculum decision-making, they don’t confuse
measuring with valuing, and they appreciate Eisner’s
insights on this matter:
Assessment and evaluation are often confounded with
measurement, but there is no necessary connection between
evaluating and measuring or between assessing and measuring.
Measuring has to do with determining magnitude. Measures of
magnitude are description of quantity. They are not appraisals
of the value of what has been measured. Assessment and
evaluation are preeminently valuative; they ask about the merits
of something. (p.180)
Given their wisdom orientation, they accept the responsibility
of practicing informed value judgments; and, like Eisner, their
evaluative focus is not on test scores but on consequences for
lifelong learning. They applaud Eisner when he writes,
“The aim of the educational process inside schools is not
to finish something, but to start something. It is not to cover
the curriculum, but to uncover it.” (p.90) And what they
want to “uncover” for their students is the
democratic good life. To paraphrase John Dewey, they believe
education is not preparation for democratic living; it is the
direct experience of this way of living (as much as circumstances
will allow).
Because they assume responsibility for the
practice of informed value judgments, these future democratic
educators are most interested in Eisner’s discussion of how
educational standards can either facilitate or inhibit curriculum
decision-making. Eisner notes that, “standards are used in
education both as values and as units of measures” (p.
168); and only when educational standards are translated into
“criteria that can be used to make judgments”
(p.173), do they support educational artistry. He writes:
“The idea of using the process of formulating standards as
a heuristic is, to me, especially appealing. It provides a focus
for discussion, deliberation, debate, analysis, and ultimately
clarification regarding the aims one wants to achieve in a
classroom, a school, or even a school district.”
(p.173)
This is exactly how the democratic educators would work. They
are interested in standards of subject matter expertise, but they
want these standards to be articulated as explicit criteria that
allow for judgments about the quality of democratic living in the
classroom, in the school, and in the school district and its
surrounding community/society. They create criteria for subject
matter understanding that reflect democratic self and social
understanding (Dewey, 1963; Henderson and Hawthorne, 2000), and
they recognize that this more holistic “3S”
approach (referring to an integrated approach to subject
matter, self and social learning) addresses what is
often “hidden” or “null” in a curriculum.
They are willing to “uncover” ugly truths about
dogmatic, authoritarian, unjust, and elitist structures and
practices.
Finally, these future democratic educators will be
most interested in Eisner’s analysis of seven
“shifts” in the current beliefs about educational
research. He argues that the following research assumptions are
increasingly problematic:
- “real” research requires
quantification…
- the experiment [is the]…way to understand the effects
of educational practice…
- the aim of research is to discover true and objective
knowledge…
- objective knowledge describes something as it really
is…
- generalizations must be statistical in character…
- research is, and can only be the result of scientific
inquiry…
- through research we will find out what works and that once we
know, it will tell us what to do and how. (pp.210-214,
author’s emphasis)
He concludes his critical analysis with the following comment:
“The ultimate implication of these shifts is not to discard
scientific research, but to recognize that it has no monopoly on
the ways in which humans inquire….” (p.214)
The future democratic educators would applaud this
conclusion. Because their curriculum decision-making is based on
“arts” of inquiry (Henderson and Kesson, 2004), they
welcome the fact that educational researchers may increasingly
work with a “more liberal conception of method.” (p.
215). They are as excited about the artistic and humanistic
possibilities of educational research as they are about the
artistic and humanistic possibilities of their own curriculum
practices. Their goal or, more accurately, their passion is to
facilitate the quality of their students’ educational
life. Research that provides deep insights into this life would,
indeed, be embraced and studied, and they would be enthusiastic
consumers of research that aspired to the inspirational heights
and poetic depths of great literature.
I have briefly presented two possible readings of
Eisner’s book. Given the complexity of his essays, many
other readings are certainly possible. He has composed a text
that is as insightful and inspirational as the educational
research he envisions.
References
Bender, T. (1993). Intellect and public life: Essays on the
social history of academic intellectuals in the United
States. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Burke, T. (1994). Dewey’s new logic: A reply to
Russell. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Cuban, L. (2003). Why is it so hard to get good
schools? New York: Teachers College Press.
Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New
York: Henry Holt and Co.
Dewey, J. (1963). Experience and education. New York:
Macmillan. (Original work published in 1938).
Dewey, J. (1989). Freedom and culture. Buffalo, NY:
Prometheus. (Original work published 1939)
Hadot, P. (2002). What is ancient philosophy?
Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Henderson, J. G., & Hawthorne, R. D. (2000).
Transformative curriculum leadership (2nd
edition). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Merrill/Prentice Hall.
Henderson, J. G., & Kesson, K. R. (2004). Curriculum
Wisdom: Educational Decisions in Democratic Societies. Upper
Saddle River, NJ: Merrill/Prentice Hall.
Kegan, R. (2000). “What “form” transforms: A
constructive-developmental approach to transformative
learning.” In J. Mezirow (Ed.), Learning as
transformation: Critical perspectives on a theory in progress
(pp. 35-69). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Klein, J. T. (1990). Interdisciplinarity: History, theory,
and practice. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.
Slattery, P., & Rapp, D. (2003). Ethics and the
foundations of education: Teaching convictions in a postmodern
world. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.
Tracy, D. (1987). Plurality and ambiguity: Hermeneutics,
religion, hope. San Francisco: Harper & Row.
About the Author
James G. Henderson is a Professor of Curriculum Studies
at Kent State University where he teaches graduate courses in
curriculum leadership and theory. His research focuses on the art
of curriculum judgment in democratic societies. He has
individually or collaboratively published over fifty essays and
books on this subject. His book, Reflective Teaching:
Professional Artistry through Inquiry, introduces teachers to
inquiry-based reflection. His co-authored book, Transformative
Curriculum Leadership, provides guidance for inspiring and
nurturing curriculum judgment. His recently completed co-authored
book, Curriculum Wisdom: Educational Decisions in Democratic
Societies, explores the arts of inquiry embedded in pragmatic
curriculum decisions.
|